Bạn đang xem bản rút gọn của tài liệu. Xem và tải ngay bản đầy đủ của tài liệu tại đây (61.25 KB, 1 trang )
500 PART 3 • Market Structure and Competitive Strategy
value, leaving us stuck in the prisoners’ dilemma. In practice, however, titfor-tat can sometimes work and cooperation can prevail. There are two primary
reasons.
First, most managers don’t know how long they will be competing with
their rivals, and this also serves to make cooperative behavior a good strategy.
If the end point of the repeated game is unknown, the unraveling argument
that begins with a clear expectation of undercutting in the last month no longer applies. As with an infinitely repeated game, it will be rational to play
tit-for-tat.
Second, my competitor might have some doubt about the extent of my
rationality. Suppose my competitor thinks (and he need not be certain)
that I am playing tit-for-tat. He also thinks that perhaps I am playing titfor-tat “blindly,” or with limited rationality, in the sense that I have failed
to work out the logical implications of a finite time horizon as discussed
above. My competitor thinks, for example, that perhaps I have not figured
out that he will undercut me in the last month, so that I should also charge
a low price in the last month, and so on. “Perhaps,” thinks my competitor,
“Firm 1 will play tit-for-tat blindly, charging a high price as long as I charge
a high price.” Then (if the time horizon is long enough), it is rational for
my competitor to maintain a high price until the last month (when he will
undercut me).
Note that we have stressed the word perhaps. My competitor need not be sure
that I am playing tit-for-tat “blindly,” or even that I am playing tit-for-tat at all.
Just the possibility can make cooperative behavior a good strategy (until near
the end) if the time horizon is long enough. Although my competitor’s conjecture about how I am playing the game might be wrong, cooperative behavior is
profitable in expected value terms. With a long time horizon, the sum of current
and future profits, weighted by the probability that the conjecture is correct,
can exceed the sum of profits from price competition, even if my competitor is
the first to undercut. After all, if I am wrong and my competitor charges a low
price, I can shift my strategy at the cost of only one period’s profit—a minor
cost in light of the substantial profit that I can make if we both choose to set a
high price.
Thus, in a repeated game, the prisoners’ dilemma can have a cooperative